Pubdate: Sat, 1 Sep 2001 Source: Social Research (NY) Copyright: 2001, New School University Contact: http://www.mapinc.org/media/1606 Website: http://www.socres.org Author: Lester Grinspoon THE HARMFULNESS TAX In the era of the Volstead Act, H. L. Mencken said of the alcohol problem that, between the distillers and saloonkeepers on the one side and the prohibitionist on the other, no intelligent person thought there was any solution at all. The same may be true of the illicit drug problem today, with its traffickers and users on one side and its moralists and police on the other. Only the problem is perhaps more serious because the acceptable range of solutions is so narrow. There is very little effective opposition to prohibition. Any serious approach to this problem (as opposed to the present futile approach) demands recognition of complexity and ambiguity. We have to reject the dream of a free society that is also drug free. We may have to acknowledge that the use of alcohol and other drugs has benefits, as well as dangers. The main obstacle to thinking about any serious alternative to present policies is that no one in government wants to give up the symbolism of the criminal law or the commitment that has been made over the last 80 years, not only in the United States but all over the world, to treating drugs as a criminal problem. I would like to suggest a proposal for a noncriminal approach to recreational drugs. Let currently controlled substances be legalized and taxed. The taxes would be used for drug education and for paying the medical and social costs of drug abuse. A regulatory agency would be established to determine these costs separately for each drug, and the rate of taxation for each drug would be adjusted periodically to reflect the information gathered by this agency. Thus, the government would acknowledge the impossibility of eliminating all drug use and use its taxing power and educational authority to encourage safer drug use. The drugs that are now legal, alcohol and tobacco, would not be distinguished from the others. To illustrate the kind of calculation involved, it was recently estimated that direct health care costs plus indirect losses in productivity and earnings due to cigarettes amount to $65 billion a year, or about $2 a pack. (The exact figures depend on how costs are defined; for example, the economic loss from smoking may be "balanced," in a perverse way, by the lowered cost of caring for chronic disabling diseases of old age in a society where many die young of smoking-related illness.) Such a taxation policy might be regarded as a way of making people buy insurance for the risks to themselves and others in their use of drugs. Life insurance companies already offer substantial discounts in their premiums for nonsmokers, an insurance preference slowly being extended to fire and other insurance policies. The program might be instituted in phases, so that we could adjust and learn more before committing ourselves fully. Phase one might involve alcohol, tobacco, and cannabis; alcohol and tobacco because they are already legal, cannabis because it is probably the least dangerous drug used for pleasure. They could all be sold through specially licensed outlets at prices determined by the regulatory agency. Advertising would be banned. Present prices might be maintained at the start. Then, as the regulatory agency collected more information, pricing would change to reflect social costs. If this system works as hoped, data would eventually indicate that these drugs are causing less and less harm. At that point we could consider bringing other drugs into the system. The advantage of this system is that we would no longer have the expense, corruption, chaos, and terror of the war between drug traffickers and narcotics agents. In this war a self-reinforcing cycle is developing as drug enforcement operations begin to pay for themselves by funds confiscated from the drug traffickers whose operations they make enormously profitable. The taxing systems suggested here would establish a different kind of revenue cycle, in which society would pay for the costs of drug abuse by extracting them from the drug users in proportion to the amount they contribute to the problem. The regulatory agency that would supervise this taxing system would also serve as an educator and guide to society-an educator not constrained by the present, totally unrealistic assumption, built into the criminal law, that any use of certain drugs must be evil or dangerous, while other drugs have a range of benign and harmful uses. Honest drug education would become possible. Is it possible that this arrangement would work? Would it be possible to tax drugs enough to pay for their costs? Even if it were possible, would drug abuse increase so much that we would be paying too high a price in personal and social misery? Is the elasticity of demand great enough so that taxing would substantially influence the amount of drugs consumed, especially by heavy users? Evidence on all this is very uncertain, even in the cases of alcohol and tobacco, where most research has been done. There is a large literature on the distribution curve of alcohol consumption among individuals in society, most of which concludes that any policy designed to cut total consumption will at least proportionally reduce alcohol use among problem drinkers and, therefore, the medical and social costs of alcohol abuse. That is, the demand is elastic enough, even among alcohol users who create problems by their use, to be affected by a rise in price. In fact there is some evidence that in countries where the price of alcohol is relatively higher, fewer alcohol problems exist, and the same is true for states within the United States. Inelasticity of demand is greatest in the case of tobacco, because nicotine is one of the most highly addicting substances. Nevertheless, it is clear that even here raising the price by taxes has considerable effect on consumption. A problem raised by any system of authorized sales is the black market. The tax would have to be set low enough so that a black market would not be profitable. It is possible to do this and still reduce demand for the drug considerably, as the case of alcohol seems to show. Yet it is not clear whether any tax low enough to prevent a substantial black market would be high enough to pay for the social and medical costs of the drug use. Certainly present taxes on alcohol are far from doing that. It might prove impossible to create a system that would make the abusers of the drug, or even its users, pay for the full costs of abuse. Maybe this problem is insoluble. Certainly the criminal law approach offers no solution for it. Many might agree that the "harmfulness tax" approach would work if it were limited to alcohol, tobacco, and cannabis. What about cocaine? Consider the present alternatives. The so-called Andean strategy of interrupting South American supplies is bound to fail for the simple reason of botany. The assumption seems to be that coca grows only in Peru, Bolivia, and Colombia. In reality, the coca bush will grow in any place were certain conditions are met: an altitude of 1,500 to 6,000 feet; continuous high humidity; a uniform average temperature of 65 degrees throughout the year; and soil free of limestone. Coca thrives on land that is too poor for other crops. In the past it has been grown commercially in Jamaica, Madagascar, India, Ceylon (Sri Lanka), and especially Java. Even if, implausibly, the coca bush could be destroyed in the Andes, it would soon be blooming again elsewhere, just as the cultivation of opium poppies increased in Iran and Afghanistan when it was curtailed in the Far East. Let us hope we do not have to see American soldiers coming home in body bags before we realize that the Andean strategy will never eliminate the supply of cocaine. No policy aimed directly at drugs and drug users can deal with the social issues that are the true heart of what is loosely, inadequately, and propagandistically labeled the "drug problem." What I am proposing is a "harmfulness tax" as an alternative to the present unsuccessful drug prohibition policy. Both legal and currently illegal drugs would be taxed in proportion to the social costs associated with their use. In a sense, drug users would be required to buy insurance against the harm that their drug use might cause to society. As was noted, the scheme would be implemented in stages, beginning with alcohol, tobacco, and marijuana. After the program had been established in this way, it would be extended to other drugs, including cocaine. This proposal accords well with experiences gained in taxing legal drugs and with the realities of current drug use in America. Lester Grinspoon, M.D., is Associate Professor of Psychiatry Emeritus at Harvard Medical School. A Fellow of both the American Association for the Advancement of Science and the American Psychiatric Association, he is founding editor of the Annual Review of Psychiatry and the Harvard Mental Health Letter. His latest book is Marihuana, the Forbidden Medicine (with James B. Bakalar, 1993). - --- MAP posted-by: Doc-Hawk